
Topology and the Foundations of Modern Mathematics 145
on a coordinate plane with the property that both coordinates are
rational numbers is an example of a set that cannot be interpreted
as a curve, surface, or volume. This set permeates the plane in the
sense that any circle, however small, will contain infinitely many
such points, but it can also be shown that almost all of the points
on the plane belong to the complement of this set. There are also
many sets composed of “abstract points” that are devoid of any
connection with geometry—sets of letters, for example, or sets of
algorithms. Statements that are true for sets in general will hold
for a very broad class of objects, and, in particular, such state-
ments will apply to geometric objects. There are, however, many
statements that one can make about geometric objects that have
no meaning outside of geometry. As the limitations of geometric
thinking became apparent, mathematicians sought an alternative
to geometry as the foundation for mathematics. Set theory seemed
the natural choice. Perhaps other choices are possible. (See the
interview with professor Scott Williams on pages 170–172, for his
description of category theory.)
The language of set theory quickly became the language of
mathematics. Many of the most prominent mathematicians of the
first half of the 20th century devoted at least some of their efforts
to the study of sets. Georg Cantor’s one-to-one correspondences,
although they were an important first step, were only the begin-
ning. Mathematicians soon discovered certain logical errors in
Cantor’s conception of what constitutes a set. Identifying and
correcting these problems and answering other questions, some
proposed by Cantor himself, constitute one of the more important
strands of 20th-century mathematical thought. As a result of all
this activity, set theory grew rapidly.
On the other hand, any theory that purports to apply to every-
thing will lack specificity. In other words, in order for a statement
to be generally true, it cannot say too much. This was certainly the
case with the theory of sets. Purely set theoretic statements were
of little use in geometry or analysis, for example, because they
lacked sufficient detail. In order to make their discoveries more
useful, mathematicians had to consider narrower classes of sets.
This is one way to understand the motivation for creating abstract