Contextual archaeology
exist in the real world – it is tangible and it is there, like
it or not. Whatever our perceptions of the world, we are
constrained by the evidence, and brought up against its con-
sequences. We reiterate that there is no test for correspon-
dence: it is instead a matter of accommodating part to whole,
or, better yet, fitting (Hodder 1999a, pp. 59–62). As the fit be-
comes tighter and as our understanding begins to fit more and
more cases, our interpretation gains ground. The hermeneutic
circles become spirals (Hodder 1992).
It is in our dialogue with each other about the success or
failure of such fusions that we learn about ourselves so that
the past contributes to the present. The attempt to fuse with
the other, as long as it is done critically and with an aware-
ness of difference and contextuality, changes our experience
and therefore changes our perspective. We would argue for
a critical hermeneutics in which interpretations are situated
historically in the past and present. But the end result is not
a debilitating relativism in which the past is viewed as largely
constructed in the present. We resist the notion that archae-
ological data represent only ‘networks of resistance’ to our
hypotheses (Shanks and Tilley 1987a, p. 104).
Nevertheless, interpretive methods for getting better and
better understandings of the past – of evaluating theories with
rigour in a post-positivist framework – have often provoked
an incredulous outcry. Many critics claim that if we accept
that data and theory are interdependent and if we encourage
multiple perspectives of the past, we will open the flood-
gates of relativism and create a maelstrom in which ‘anything
goes’: in which all firm grounds for contesting abominable
(fascist, racist, sexist, etc.) interpretations and uses of the past
are washed away. For the most part, these claims are rudder-
less: they result in some cases from blatant misreadings of key
post-positivist texts and in other cases from the purposefully
ambiguous, shifty nature of the post-positivist texts them-
selves. However, the spectre of relativism endures (Renfrew
2001), perhaps because it is not easy, even for the most epis-
temologically astute, to explain how the dichotomy between
relativism and objectivism can be overcome.
199