FromJeremyBenthamtoJ.S.Mill
In 1802 Bentham was fifty-three years old, but hardly at the pinnacle
of his career. His great practical project, the Panopticon prison system, on
which he had devoted so much time and energy, was doomed to failure
(see Semple 1993). If one considers his writings just prior to the appearance
of the Tra i t
´
es, they seem to be confined to issues surrounding Panopticon,
the poor laws and economic policy (see Bentham 1984,pp.487–8). In the
decades following its publication he began a number of works of philosoph-
ical significance, such as the writings on evidence and judicial procedure,
codification, education, logic, language, fallacies, religion, ethics and psy-
chology. Much of this material, covering thousands of manuscript folios,
looked back to the Tr a i t
´
es, which in turn provided a window to Bentham’s
earliest publications, such as A Fragment on Government (1776)andIPML,
which had been virtually forgotten by this time.
The Trait
´
es possesses an additional significance for this essay in that the
answer given by Robson to the question, ‘Which Bentham was Mill’s
Bentham?’ (‘if forced to answer in one word’) is ‘Dumont’s’ (Robson 1993,
i,p.206). For the Tr ait
´
es, read by Mill in 1821, was a major feature in his
earliest study of Bentham (see Robson 1993, i,p.197). Mill’s interest in the
Tra it
´
es was probably enhanced by the fact that he read it after his return from
France, where he acquired a fluency in that language during his visit with
Samuel Bentham’s (1757–1831) family (see Robson 1993, i,p.205; see also
Mill 1981, CWM, i,pp.577). It is arguable that the Tr a i t
´
es formed a lens
through which Mill read much of Bentham, and it focused Mill’s ideas in a
particular manner.
To the one-word answer to his question, Robson then added a footnote:
‘There is a major implication here that makes me a bit uneasy: i.e., that
Mill’s Bentham is the Continental (and indeed international) Bentham. Was
there, in Bentham’s lifetime at least, a significant English Bentham (one not
seen through Dumont)?’ (Robson 1993, i,p.208n). To this further question,
left unanswered by Robson, a provisional answer will be attempted here.
Dumont’s recensions presented Bentham mainly as a philosopher and jurist
and as a bridge from the Enlightenment to nineteenth-century thought.
Bentham’s radical, democratic views, particularly prominent after 1809–10
in his manuscripts and after 1817
with the publication of Plan
of Parliamentary
Reform, were of little importance to Dumont (see Dinwiddy 1992b, pp. 297–
9). If Mill’s Bentham was that of Dumont, Mill’s conception of philosophic
radicalism would have to deal with this discrepancy. As we shall see, Mill
attempted to reject Benthamite political radicalism (and what he saw as
its narrow self-regarding foundations) while at the same time adopting
259