nineteenth-century france: from staël to baudelaire 97
the world around him is not, for Gautier, escapist but a refusal to be
distracted by non-artistic matters, and thus a guarantee of his aesthetic
integrity. This is startlingly different from earlier criticism of works
in the elevated classical tradition. Critical responses to the work of
Ingres’s own teacher, David, rarely failed to stress its politically, socially,
or morally elevating aspects (as we have seen in Cousin’s praise of
David’s Socrates, 40).
Thus in Gautier’s writing Ingres’s art becomes the ultimate example
of art’s autonomy, as it had been theorized with progressive clarity
from hints in Kant, through Staël’s repudiation of the ‘useful’, to
Cousin’s insistence that art should have an intrinsic value equivalent to
that of religion or morality. Indeed it may have been the passage from
Cousin’s lecture series of 1818, quoted on page 75, that coined the motto
under which this art theory became notorious: l’art pour l’art.
47
In his
writing on Ingres Gautier perhaps adapts Cousin’s notion of art as a
kind of religion in itself: ‘Closed voluntarily in the depths of the sanc-
tuary . . . the author of . . . the Vow of Louis XIII has lived in the ecstatic
contemplation of the beautiful, on his knees before Phidias and
Raphael, his gods; pure, austere, fervent, meditative, and producing in
freedom works testifying to his faith.’
48
Such language has often been
seen to promote some kind of transcendent value for art, elevating it
above real-world political and social issues. Yet the passage can also be
read as recommending a very modern replacement of the spiritual
claims of traditional religion with the material and sensuous immedi-
acy of art in the here-and-now. This can also help to explain the
important role implicitly accorded to the erotic in Gautier’s writing:
the vocabularies of both religion and eroticism are used to indicate the
exceptional power of the sensuous experience of beauty.
In 1847, Gautier contributed an article to the Revue des Deux
Mondes, which presents the fullest explication of his theory: ‘L’art pour
l’art signifies, for its adherents, a work disengaged from all other pre-
occupation than that of the beautiful in itself ’. Gautier takes Kant to
task for failing to give sufficient emphasis to sensuous experience.
Acknowledging that it is a ‘noble and grand idea’ to make beauty a
matter of the human mind, as Kant did, he wonders whether this does
not ‘suppress too decidedly the material world’. Moreover, he supports
this with an argument similar to Ingres’s: the artist, he writes, has no
‘alphabet’ of forms except that of the visible world, so the beautiful
cannot be purely subjective.
49
In fact Kant had strongly emphasized
that the aesthetic response, although it occurs in the mind, could only
come about through sensory experience. For Kant, as for Gautier and
Ingres, human beings have only the five terrestrial senses and cannot
have access to a supersensible realm; it was, as we have seen, in the
interpretations of Staël and Cousin that the experience of the beautiful
acquired intimations of transcendence. It seems likely that Gautier