nineteenth-century france: from staël to baudelaire 105
in a frenzy of inspiration to reduce the time lag to a minimum: ‘skir-
mishing with his pencil, his pen, his brush, splashing his glass of water
up to the ceiling, wiping his pen on his shirt, in a ferment of violent
activity, as though afraid that the image might escape him’. But already
it is an ‘image’ in his mind, a step removed from the raw experience of
the scene. When it is ‘reborn upon his paper’ it is removed another step:
‘The phantasmagoria has been distilled from nature. All the raw mat-
erials with which the memory has loaded itself are put in order, ranged
and harmonized, and undergo that forced idealization which is the
result of a childlike perceptiveness. . . .’
63
The words ‘memory’ and
‘idealization’ immediately remind us of Delacroix. Baudelaire has
succeeded, then, in showing how Guys’s ephemeral sketches partake
after all of the eternal element of beauty. More than that, he has
also proved his first point: that the transient element—the powerful
modernity of the drawing—is inconceivable without the eternal one.
And that goes not only for the drawing itself; it is true, too, of Guys’s
original aesthetic experience of the scene, and of our experience of the
drawing.
Indeed, Baudelaire gives this special emphasis, for he insists (despite
some evidence to the contrary) that Guys did not make his drawings
while he was actually looking at the scene, but instead used a two-stage
process: first, drinking in visual experience as intensively as possible, to
imprint it on his memory; then, drawing on the memory later to trans-
form it into the drawing. We have seen Delacroix employing some
such method in the production of a complex oil painting [48]. The
example of Guys’s drawings gives Baudelaire a kind of limit case, in
which our experience of the represented scene is both as direct as we
can feasibly imagine, and yet already mediated twice through the
‘eternal’ aspect of beauty. The example of Guys also tests the limits of
the problem Kant had raised about the intentionality of the artist.
Guys’s working method, as Baudelaire describes it, comes as close as
possible to unpremeditated production: it is ‘as unconscious and spon-
taneous as is digestion for a healthy man after dinner’. Yet every time
Baudelaire suggests the pure immediacy—or modernity—of the
process, he qualifies the notion.
64
So spontaneous is the process that no
step in the making of the drawing can be seen as a mere stage on the
way towards some more final resolution of the drawing—that would
imply that there was a plan or goal towards which the artist was
aiming. Therefore, each set of marks, the initial pencil notation, the
washes added next, the firm contours drawn later, is an end in itself: ‘at
no matter what stage in its execution, each drawing has a sufficiently
“finished” look; call it a “study” if you will, but you will have to admit
that it is a perfect study’.
65
Thus not only the final drawing, but the
drawing in progress, with every addition of a mark, is both utterly tran-
sient (modern) and utterly finished (eternal).