
Political
philosophy
407
thus rendered compatible with the rising absolutism of
early
seventeenth-
century
Europe.
Conservative
though the Spanish theologians may have been in their
theory
of
imperium,
there was one topic on which they adopted a
remarkably
radical stance,
while
managing at the same time to extend the
traditional
subject-matter
of
political philosophy. This was in relation to the
conduct
of their fellow-countrymen as colonists in the New World. To
many
contemporary observers, Spain's policy of annexation and enslave-
ment appeared to pose no special problems of political morality. The
earliest
political Aristotelians had generally taken it for granted that, in the
words
of
Giles
of
Rome,
Aristotle had 'proved' that 'some people
are
slaves
by
nature,
and that it is appropriate for such people to be placed in
subjection to others'.
86
Licensed by such high authority, the category of
'slaves by
nature'
came to be widely used in the course of the sixteenth
century
to justify the behaviour of the Spanish imperialists. At a special
conference
on the issue convened by the
emperor
at
Valladolid in
15
50,
Juan
Gines de Sepulveda argued that, since the Indians possessed no knowledge
of
the Christian faith, they deserved to be categorised as 'slaves by
nature'
whose way
of
life
was one of'natural rudeness and inferiority'. The Spanish
conquests, he concluded, ought in consequence to be viewed as
a
just war
against
infidels,
while
the policy
of
enslaving the local inhabitants ought to
be recognised as a helpful means
of
converting them.
87
Haifa century later
this remained the view of such theocratic writers as Campanella, whose
Monarchia
messiae
includes
a
further defence
of
the
Spanish conquests on the
grounds of their contribution to the spread of Christianity.
88
To
the Thomist theologians, however, and above all to Vitoria, such
arguments
seemed to overlook an even more
crucial
Aristotelian category:
that
of
the
'perfect society', with its own chosen form
of
dominium,
which it
is open to any group of people to establish, without benefit of revelation,
simply on the basis of their natural understanding of the rules
of
justice.
Armed
with this concept, Vitoria proceeds to develop a courageous and
thoroughgoing defence of the Indians in a long essay entitled De
Indis
recenter
inventis. The crucial question, he begins by affirming, is 'whether
these barbarians were
true
lords in relation to private and public affairs
before
the coming
of
the
Spanish'.
89
His answer is that 'without doubt these
barbarians
were
true
rulers,
both in public and private affairs, no
less
than if
86. Giles of
Rome
1607, p. 380 (11.3.13):
'quod
aliqui
sunt
naturaliter
servi,
et
quod
expedit
aliquibus
aliis
esse
subiectos'.
87. Hanke 1959, p. 44. But for a
different
(not
wholly
convincing)
interpretation
of servus see
Fernandez-Santamaria 1977, pp.
209-14.
88. Campanella
i960,
pp. 74-5 (cap. 15).
89. Vitoria 1933-6,11, p. 292 (1.4):
'utrum
barbari
isti
essent
veri
domini
ante
adventum
Hispanorum
et
privatim et
publice'.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008