
The intellective soul
525
and eternal, intellective parts.
297
The rational soul could only assist the
human body, which was formed by the cogitative soul, and was linked to it
like
a captain to his ship or the intelligence to its sphere, through its
operations.
298
Since intellection was the operation of the rational soul, it
was
not just one
—
albeit the highest
—
act of man, but
rather
the dynamic
linkage
that
ensured the unity both of man and of the entire universe.
The
structure
of
this unifying process
of
intellection had,
of
course, to be
modelled on the structure of the universe itself,
that
is, participation. And
this was the moment when Aristotle entered the picture. His distinction
between agent and possible intellect, supplemented by the habitual intellect
from the tradition
of
Simplicius
and Averroes, offered the
three
terms
of
the
model.
299
The
intellect, so long as it remained in itself (then called the intellectus
manens)
was one and eternal; proceeding towards the secondary
lives,
the
vitae secundae, of animality, it
turned
into the rational soul or the intellectus
progressus. As such, it extended between the eternal and the corruptible and
included
three
aspects: (1) in so far as it still participated in the intellectus
manens, it was the agent intellect, containing in itself all the intelligible
species
and universal forms; (2) in so far as it proceeded to the human
individual, it was the possible intellect, able to receive the intelligible species
from the agent intellect; and (3) in so far as it had already received some of
these species, it was the habitual intellect or the perfection of the possible
intellect. Once all intelligible species had been received, the last of these
ceased - along with the possible intellect - to be a distinct
part
of
the rational
soul,
so
that,
as a whole, it became identical with the agent intellect, or
rather
with the intellectus manens, which was an eternal intelligence.
300
Intellection was
thus
the process through which the intellectus progressus
returned to the intellectus manens. Since with this
return
the intellectus
progressus vanished, in the question on the immortality of the soul, which
was
published separately in
1565,
Genua did not hesitate to maintain
that
the
one intellectus
manens
was immortal, while the different aspects of the
intellectus progressus perished along with the body.
301
The problem which
still
remained to be solved, however, was how the material and the
immaterial cooperated in this intellective process and thereby constituted
the unity of the universe. Traditionally - and Genua was
well
aware of
contradicting the common opinion
of
nearly all the commentators
302
—
the
297. Ibid., ff.
36
vb
-7
vb
(lib. 11 ad t. c. n);
Nardi
1958, p. 389.
298.
Genua
1576, f.
37
rb
(lib. 11 ad t. c. 11); f.
i28
rb
(lib. 111 ad t. c. 2); f. 185™ (lib. in ad t. c. 39).
299. Ibid., f.
i52
vb
(lib. in ad t. c. 17). 300. Ibid., ff.
i52
vb
-4
ra
(lib. m ad t. c. 17).
301. Ibid., ff.
i83
rb
-9
vb
(lib. in ad t. c. 39);
Genua
1565.
302.
Genua
1576, f. 155
ra
(lib. m ad t. c. 18).
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008