
HISTORY 603
The ultimate value of Mencius, then, was the existential emphasis
given to human virtue as never static, and not an absolute to be recov-
ered through diligent meditation or study. Virtue was constantly being
acted out by ordinary individuals
as a
continuous part of human history,
in small and unspectacular ways that never led to final resolutions, as in
total enlightenment. It was best to speak of the "way," Jinsai thus
concluded, not as an ultimate and unchanging reason but as small
pathways that human beings journeyed over in daily life, with compas-
sion, fairness, humility, and truthfulness. This included for Jinsai a
healthy appreciation of the inevitable human
passions,
jo, of fear, sad-
ness,
joy, and anger as essential to human life. The active tendency
toward goodness was thus to be found in the actual world of work, play,
learning, and commerce without regard to distinctions previously im-
posed by metaphysical and political hierarchies. Through Jinsai,
Mencius took
on a
fresh moral and intellectual cogency among common-
ers often not adequately appreciated by historians of thought. Through
Mencius, ancient text had framed action in the present at whatever
level
in society that could be moral in a universally human sense.
Ogyu Sorai found much in Jinsai's thinking to admire, especially as
he too had independently reached similar conclusions regarding the
unreliability of Neo-Confucian metaphysics, the centrality of historical
genius as the proper source of moral knowledge, and the importance
of leaving the present and identifying with that genetic moment.
Sorai, moreover, did not dispute Jinsai's propensity to see virtue in
human action at all levels of society. He disagreed profoundly, how-
ever, on where the ultimate genesis of moral knowledge should be
located and on what this knowledge should clarify in the first and most
fundamental instance. Whereas Jinsai directed his historicism to ex-
pand the spaces for universal moral action among commoners, stress-
ing the horizontality of human potential, Sorai insisted that this per-
spective did not address the question of why there was hierarchy and
governance at all, and what these meant to history and to the ongoing
present as a moral field.
Sorai's admiration for Jinsai, therefore, was qualified on firm con-
ceptual grounds, as he reiterated in his key writings on the way and on
names -
Bendd
and Benmei.
1
He expressed particular dissatisfaction
7 The Bendd and Benmei are in Yoshikawa Kojiro and Maruyama Masao, eds., Ogyu Sorai, vol.
36 of Nihon shiso taikei (Tokyo: Iwanami shoten, 1973). See also Bito Masahide, ed., Ogyu
Sorai, vol. 16 of Nihon no meicho (Tokyo: Chuo koronsha, 1974). See also Tahara Tsuguo,
Tokugawa shisoshi kenkyu (Tokyo: Miraisha, 1967); Imanaka Kanshi, Soraigaku no kisoteki
kenkyu (Tokyo: Yoshikawa kobunkan, 1966); Hixaishi Naoaki, Ogyu Sorai
nempuko
(Tokyo:
Heibonsha, 1984); J. R. McEwan, The Political
Writings
of Ogyu Sorai (Cambridge, England:
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008