HIERARCHY
— 398—
History of the concept
The ancient Greek philosopher Plato has had an
enormous influence on hierarchical thinking. In
works such as the Republic and Phaedo, Plato ar-
gued that the world is divided into a lower, chaotic
material reality, and a higher reality of forms that is
the genuine source of truth, beauty, and the good.
For Plato, this ontological distinction was neces-
sarily related to epistemological and moral ones,
for the realm of the forms are the source of true
knowledge as well as being the ultimate good that
all seek. Human beings were seen as a composite
of the two worlds, the irrational world of matter
and the rational world of the forms. In Plato’s
framework, the good person is one who shuns ma-
terial things and pursues rational inquiry in accor-
dance with one’s true, nonmaterial nature.
During the Roman era, Plotinus (205–270) and
other neo-Platonists expanded Plato’s dualism into
what twentieth-century philosopher Arthur Lovejoy
(1873–1962) called the great chain of being. Ac-
cording to this view, God is the most real, out of
which all other things emanate. Material reality is
that which is most distant from the plenitude of
God and, in a sense, the least real. As a composite
of the different levels of reality, human beings
stand at a halfway point, both material and spiri-
tual. Neo-Platonism profoundly influenced the de-
velopment of Christian theology, particularly
through the writings of Augustine of Hippo (354–
430), Pseudo-Dionysus (c. fifth century
C.E.), and
Bonaventure (1217–1274). In a Christian frame-
work, angels naturally fit into a neo-Platonic frame-
work as beings who occupied a higher level of re-
ality. For Augustine in particular, evil could be
explained as the absence of good, an irrational
move from the most real (God) towards the unreal.
The rise of modern science played a significant
role in the demise of hierarchical understandings of
the world. Early scientific thinkers were influenced
by philosophers such as William of Ockham (c.
1285–c. 1347), who denied Plato’s theory of forms
and hierarchical ontologies. This and other factors
led to an understanding of the physical world that
emphasized material causes alone, a tendency that
seemed vindicated by the work of Galileo Galilei
(1564–1642) and Isaac Newton (1642–1727). Such
materialistic views were typically reductionistic in
character. Materialist reductionists inverted and
then rejected the neo-Platonic hierarchy of being,
claiming not only that it is the material world that is
most real, it is the only reality. Such materialism not
only influenced scientists such as Pierre-Simon
Laplace (1749–1827), but also the whole trajectory
of nineteenth-century philosophy.
In the twentieth century, the legitimacy of on-
tological and moral hierarchies was intensely de-
bated within specific fields of philosophy and the-
ology. Debates about ontological hierarchies
focused on questions of reductionism and emer-
gence or holism, much of which centered on the
status of the mind and human person. Reduction-
ists emphasize that the material constituents of the
world are all that there is, and that higher-order re-
alities such as the human mind and culture can ul-
timately be explained by the laws of physics and
chemistry. Reductionists often point to the success
of neo-Darwinism and the discovery of DNA as
justification for their approach. Likewise, categories
of mind and the human person, so reductionists
argue, can best be understood in terms of the ac-
tivities of the brain. In the late twentieth century,
reductionism was most associated with the popular
writings of Richard Dawkins and Francis Crick in
biology and the thought of Daniel Dennett, Paul
Churchland, and Patricia Churchland in the philos-
ophy of mind.
Modern opposition to reductionism has early
roots in the movement of British emergentism, typ-
ified by the work of C. D. Broad. Opponents to re-
ductionism have frequently endorsed the category
of emergence, arguing that there are higher-order
levels that emerge from, but are not reducible to,
the lower levels of reality. Generally speaking,
emergentists do not deny the validity of the lower-
level sciences, only their sufficiency for explaining
higher-order phenomenon. Emergentism came to
be particularly important for the defense of biology
as a legitimate and separate field of inquiry from
physics and chemistry, and has been vigorously
supported by such prominent thinkers as biologist
Ernst Mayr and philosopher Karl Popper. Emer-
gence has also been complemented by the concept
of supervenience, which provides a philosophical
framework for understanding the relation of differ-
ent levels of reality. Philosophers such as Jaegwon
Kim have argued, however, that supervenience ul-
timately leads to causal reduction of higher-level to
lower-level physical properties. Within the para-
digm of computational complexity theory, a similar
suspicion has been raised against emergence by
John Holland and others.