GENETIC ENGINEERING
— 361—
knowledge of genes is discovery, not invention,
and should not be eligible for patent protection.
Many have also argued that granting biological
patents amounts to patenting life, therefore making
life a mere commodity. Other religious scholars
recognize that patenting, while not perfect, is es-
sential to the financial development of the full po-
tential of genetic engineering, and that opposition
to patenting is tantamount to opposing the benefits
of research.
Beyond these general concerns, many reli-
gious scholars and organizations have considered
developments in genetic engineering on a case-by-
case basis. For instance, many religious organiza-
tions have responded to the use of genetic engi-
neering to modify food by recognizing its potential
for increasing the quality and quantity of food, but
with cautions having to do with the viability of
small farms, global inequities, the power of corpo-
rations in view of intellectual property rights, and
the right of consumers to know what they are eat-
ing. Similarly, religious scholars have raised con-
cerns, but generally have not objected categori-
cally, to genetic engineering of animals. Of special
concern is the prospect of herds of genetically
identical livestock becoming vulnerable to disease,
or to the use of genetic engineering to create
strains of animals whose sole purpose is to suffer
a disease for the benefit of medical research.
Quite understandably, human applications
evoke the most intense religious responses. Reli-
gious responses to the use of genetic engineering
for pharmaceutical purposes have been positive,
with concerns limited to patenting, to the high
costs of medicines, and to the need for socially just
patterns of distribution. Furthermore, almost with-
out exception, human gene therapy has met with
approval not just by the public, but by religious in-
stitutions and scholars, who assess it morally as an
extension of traditional medicine. Issues of safety
remain, and many are concerned that the tech-
nique, when shown to be beneficial, will not be
justly distributed.
The greatest concern, however, is that the
technique will not be limited in its application to
therapy but will be used for enhancement of
human health and possibly of traits that are unre-
lated to health. Those who voice this concern
point not just to cosmetic surgery and to perform-
ance enhancing drugs in sports but to the use of
mood-altering pharmaceutical products, such as
the drugs known as selective serotonin reuptake
inhibitors (SSRIs). Evidence exists that people re-
quest these drugs not to treat anxiety or depression
but to improve their mood and thus their perform-
ance in life. If that is true, some argue, how much
more will people request gene modification that
enhances their state of being and their perform-
ance. As of 2002, it is not at all clear which human
traits will become susceptible to enhancement by
genetic engineering. Height, most definitely, will
be modifiable, but perhaps mental and emotional
traits may be modifiable too. The concern here is
the lack clarity about the distinction between ther-
apy and enhancement, and thus the lack any pub-
licly credible way to prevent those with economic
or political means from acquiring new ways to im-
prove themselves to the competitive disadvantage
of others.
Sometime in the twenty-first century, many be-
lieve, humans will learn how to modify the genes
of their offspring. Such germline modification, as it
is usually called, is already done in other mam-
mals, although not reliably. Many technical obsta-
cles lie ahead, but learning to do this in human be-
ings has a strong attraction, for some, in the
promise that a family might be freed of a genetic
disease that has afflicted it for generations. Other
techniques, such as testing an embryo for disease
before it is implanted, will probably achieve the
same result at less cost and risk. If so, it may turn
out that the real advantage of germline modifica-
tion is not to eliminate disease but to improve the
next generation, perhaps by enhancing resistance
to disease or by producing other traits. The
prospect of children born with such enhancement,
often referred to as designer babies, is widely op-
posed by the general public, secular scholars, and
religious leaders, even though most analysts con-
cede that it probably cannot be prevented.
Religious objections to germline modification
are that the resulting children will enter the world
as objects, engineered according to the will of their
designers and not as persons who emerge from
the love of their parents. The intrusion of technol-
ogy perverts the relationship between parent and
child, difficult under any circumstance, but all the
more so if parents can use technology to express
their desires for the kind of child they want to
have. Others believe that designed children will
face impossible expectations in achieving that for