LANGUAGE
— 505—
evolutionary track from other African apes for at
least five million years, that members of species
similar enough to be included in the genus Homo
have been around for 1.8 million years, and that the
human species Homo sapiens is at least two hun-
dred thousand years old. In general, these earliest
samples of expressive symbolism must be under-
stood not as evidence for the initial evolution of
symbolic abilities but rather for their first expression
in durable media. They likely had long been incor-
porated into conventionalized social activities by
that time. The origins of the symbolic traditions that
these works express in material form could easily
anticipate this data by an order of magnitude.
To get some idea of the possible extremes of
this range of possible dates consider the following.
The earliest direct archeological evidence of lan-
guage is, of course, in the form of early forms of
writing, which are all less than ten thousand years
old, and most considerably more recent (about five
thousand years ago). Since not even the most rad-
ical theorists among archeologists and paleontolo-
gists would date the appearance of modern lan-
guages more recently than about fifty thousand
years ago, this late externalization of language of-
fers a curious challenge: Why did it take so long
for this most important means of communication to
exhibit direct external expression? The same ques-
tion can be asked of the first evidence of pictorial
and carved forms, which date back about sixty
thousand years in Europe and Australia and possi-
bly earlier in Africa (though this African evidence is
currently less well known). Assuming some com-
parable difficulties in externalizing these different
modes of symbolic expression, we might suggest
that, most conservatively, the corresponding dis-
tinctively human symbolic communication must be
at least ten times as old; that is, 5,000 to 50,000
years for modern language, and 50,000 to 500,000
years for some form of language.
At the other end of the spectrum, there is a se-
ries of apparently linked paleontological transitions
evident between 1.6 and 2.4 million years ago in
Africa that suggest that the beginnings of symbolic
communications in some form may date to this fos-
sil epoch. The first clear evidence for the regular
production of stone choppers, at a site called Gona,
can be dated to about 2.4 million years ago. These
are associated with fossil species of the genus Aus-
tralopithecus (possibly A. garhi). Australopithecines
exhibited ape-sized brains, relatively large jaws
with heavy dentition (evidence of a vegetarian di-
etary adaptation), relatively modern bipedal loco-
motion, and also a characteristic sexual dimorphism
(males much larger on average than females),
which is indicative of male competition over fe-
males in a polygynous mating system that is fairly
typical of monkeys and great apes. By 1.8 million
years ago a number of fossil sites begin to demon-
strate hominid species with larger brains and re-
duced dentition, correlated with extensive stone
tool assemblages. These features have prompted
paleontologists to cite this as the point where our
genus, Homo, begins. By 1.6 million years ago
members of our genus, with brains beginning to
cross into the low end of the modern range, had
left Africa to spread into Asia, Southeast Asia, and
possibly throughout more temperate Asian regions
as well, taking with them more sophisticated tools.
Given these unprecedented features, there can be
little doubt that some significant changes in com-
munication and cognition also are contemporane-
ous with these transitions—the first forms of crude
symbolic communication—though it is likely that
the evolution of modern forms of linguistic com-
munication took much longer to develop.
If symbolic communication has been around in
some form for as much as two million years then
we can expect it to have had significant conse-
quences not just for human culture but also for
human brain function. The evolutionary biological
effect of a behavioral adaptation such as this may
be usefully compared to that of dam building in
North American beavers. The evolution of this abil-
ity has changed the niche in which beavers mature
and live, and this has changed the natural selection
forces affecting beaver physiology and behavioral
propensities in succeeding generations. Thus,
beavers exhibit extensive aquatic adaptations as a
feed-forward result of beaver behaviors. This evo-
lutionary process has been called niche construc-
tion. The effects of human symbolic communica-
tion and culture can also be understood as a form
of niche construction, though symbolic culture is
in many ways a far more all-encompassing niche
than a beaver pond. This niche likely favored the
evolution of certain cognitive capacities and social
predispositions relevant to symbolic learning and
communication, but also, as in the case of beavers,
there may be many special features of this artificial
niche that are idiosyncratic to it. Thus, there is
good reason to expect that human brains have