
19 1.8 Particularly important results
t
(y)
2
− (z)
2
. This overall sign is a matter of convention (like the use of Latin and Greek
indices we referred to earlier), since invariance of s
2
implies invariance of −s
2
.The
physical result of importance is just this invariance, which arises from the difference in
sign between the (t)
2
and [(x)
2
+ (y)
2
+ (z)
2
] parts. As with other conventions,
students should ensure they know which sign is being used: it affects all sorts of formulae,
for example Eq. (1.9).
Failure of relativity?
Newcomers to SR, and others who don’t understand it well enough, often worry at this
point that the theory is inconsistent. We began by assuming the principle of relativity, which
asserts that all observers are equivalent. Now we have shown that if
¯
O moves relative to O,
the clocks of
¯
O will be measured by O to be running more slowly than those of O.Soisn’t
it therefore the case that
¯
O will measure O ’s clocks to be running faster than his own? If
so, this violates the principle of relativity, since we could as easily have begun with
¯
O and
deduced that O’s clocks run more slowly than
¯
O’s.
This is what is known as a ‘paradox’, but like all ‘paradoxes’ in SR, this comes from
not having reasoned correctly. We will now demonstrate, using spacetime diagrams, that
¯
O measures O’s clocks to be running more slowly. Clearly, we could simply draw the
spacetime diagram from
¯
O’s point of view, and the result would follow. But it is more
instructive to stay in O’s spacetime diagram.
Different observers will agree on the outcome of certain kinds of experiments. For exam-
ple, if A flips a coin, every observer will agree on the result. Similarly, if two clocks are
right next to each other, all observers will agree which is reading an earlier time than the
other. But the question of the rate at which clocks run can only be settled by comparing
the same two clocks on two different occasions, and if the clocks are moving relative to
one another, then they can be next to each other on only one of these occasions. On the
other occasion they must be compared over some distance, and different observers may
draw different conclusions. The reason for this is that they actually perform different and
inequivalent experiments. In the following analysis, we will see that each observer uses two
of his own clocks and one of the other’s. This asymmetry in the ‘design’ of the experiment
gives the asymmetric result.
Let us analyze O’s measurement first, in Fig. 1.14. This consists of comparing the read-
ing on a single clock of
¯
O (which travels from A to B) with two clocks of his own: the
first is the clock at the origin, which reads
¯
O’s clock at event A; and the second is the
clock which is at F at t = 0 and coincides with
¯
O’s clock at B. This second clock of O
moves parallel to the first one, on the vertical dashed line. What O says is that both clocks
at A read t = 0, while at B the clock of
¯
O reads
¯
t = 1,
while that of O reads a later time,
t = (1 −v
2
)
−1/2
. Clearly,
¯
O agrees with this, as he is just as capable of looking at clock
dials as O is. But for O to claim that
¯
O’s clock is running slowly, he must be sure that
his own two clocks are synchronized, for otherwise there is no particular significance in
observing that at B the clock of
¯
O lags behind that of O.Now,fromO’s point of view, his