EXPERIENCE,RELIGIOUS:PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS
— 312—
through rites and mortifications. An enthusiast, by
contrast, ignorant of the physiological cause of un-
warranted hope or pride, attributes it to divine in-
spiration and experiences transports, raptures, and
ecstasies. In both cases the subject resorts to imag-
inary causes to satisfy an explanatory interest.
Hume believed that the proportions of super-
stition and enthusiasm in a religion had important
social consequences. He argued that superstition
requires priests to interpose on behalf of the
cowed fearful, whereas enthusiasm will not abide
priests because the enthusiast believes his sacred
commerce with God obviates institutions and their
representatives. Enthusiastic religions begin tumul-
tuously, even violently, but quickly moderate be-
cause their weak institutional structure cannot sus-
tain the fervor. Nevertheless, enthusiasm’s spirit of
self-reliance and autonomy bolsters civil liberty.
Superstition, by contrast, gains ground gradually
by taming its adherents and ends in tyranny. De-
spite the fact that Hume emphasizes only the in-
fluence an individual’s emotions have on his reli-
gion and overlooks the extent to which the
doctrines of a religion inform the quality of the in-
dividual’s emotions, his account is superior to
many later theories for at least one major reason.
Hume stresses the cognitive nature of religious ex-
perience, that explanatory commitments are con-
stitutive of religious experience. The subject’s own
tacit or implicit commitments about the proper ex-
planation of the experience are what makes the
experience the experience it is. Many later theo-
rists, including James, elide this feature of religious
experience.
Polemics and apologetics
Hume’s theory had a polemical tenor. He labeled
both superstition and enthusiasm “species of false
religion” (p. 73), and the essay has a political sub-
text. Hume is instructive in this regard. The study
of religious experience, like the study of religion it-
self, had its origin in polemics and apologetics.
This history explains the contours of the concept.
Religious experience was forged in response to the
modern challenge to religion. Since the Enlighten-
ment, rational inquiry had impugned the traditional
sources of religious knowledge. Baruch Spinoza
(1632–1677) and the subsequent development of
higher textual criticism undermined scriptural au-
thority. The creation of modern probability theory
eroded the once intrinsic connection between doc-
trinal authority and credibility. Hume and Im-
manuel Kant (1724–1804) effectively thwarted the
aspiration for natural theology, while Hume, fur-
thermore, produced what he called a “check”
against the credibility of miracle claims. By way of
rejoinder, apologists turned to spiritual or mystical
experience as a ground for religious commitment.
They argued that religious experience is cogni-
tively immediate (i.e., not influenced by, or a prod-
uct of, prior beliefs) and, therefore, unassailable by
rational and historical inquiry into the defensibility
of religious beliefs. If religious experience were, in
part, a product of prior religious beliefs, one could
not use religious experience as an independent
ground for religious commitment. Armed with this
understanding of religious experience, the increas-
ing exposure to the vast diversity of religions pre-
sented not a challenge, but a defense in numbers.
Despite incompatible beliefs and practices, all reli-
gions at bottom stem from the same or similar ex-
periences, feelings, or sentiments.
Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768–1834) inaugu-
rated this apologetic conception of religious expe-
rience. In On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured De-
spisers (1799) he explained that religion consists in
piety, a distinct moment of consciousness that he
construed as “a sense or taste for the Infinite.” In his
later systematic theology, The Christian Faith
(1830) he described piety as the “feeling of absolute
dependence” that accompanies all self-conscious-
ness. In both works he sharply distinguished piety
from belief and insisted on the immediacy of piety.
Ultimately, he heralded an “eternal covenant” be-
tween science and religion, whereby religion al-
lows to science all that is of interest to it (1981, pp.
64–65). The immediate, noncognitive nature of
piety, he claimed, eliminated the possibility of a
conflict. The tendency to treat religious experience
as immediate and to consider it the source of reli-
gion became widespread after Schleiermacher. De-
spite James’s refusal to distinguish sharply between
feelings and beliefs in his more psychological and
philosophical works, he too displays this tendency
in The Varieties of Religious Experience when he
claims that personal religious feelings are immedi-
ate, primordial, and ultimately productive of beliefs.
Naturalistic explanations of religious experi-
ence, such as Hume’s, had their effect on the con-
cept of religious experience as well. Ann Taves, in
her book Fits, Trances, and Visions (1999) has