
340
Moral philosophy
temperate, his moderation being in relation to corporeal pleasure, not to
temperance itself.
214
The
Platonist Pletho objected to the Peripatetic doctrine of the mean
because he believed
that
it was measured in terms of quantity
rather
than
quality. He claimed
that
Aristotle determined which things were appro-
priate to fear on the basis
of
how
great or small they were. Platonists, on the
other hand, used quality as their sole criterion: whatever was dishonourable
was
to be feared, no matter how great or small it was; similarly, whatever
was
not dishonourable was not to be feared, regardless of size or
quantity.
215
According to
Fox-Morcillo,
however,
there
was no significant
disagreement between Platonists and Peripatetics on this issue. For although
Plato himself never mentioned this doctrine, both Apuleius and Albinus
confirmed
that
he, like Aristotle, had thought
that
virtue was situated in the
middle
of
two
vices.
216
Fox-Morcillo
himself
was
only in partial agreement
with
this
view.
He thought
there
were
three
different types of emotions:
those which were by
nature
good, such as benevolence and pity; those which
were always bad, such as hatred and envy; and those which were neutral,
such asjoy or fear. The mean did not apply to emotions in the first category,
which
retained their goodness whether they were excessive or deficient; nor
to the second, which even when restrained were wicked; but only to the
third,
which when moderate were virtues but when extreme were
vices.
217
Theophilus Golius made a similar distinction, which he applied to actions as
well
as emotions. The doctrine
of
the mean was not relevant to those actions
which
were per se good, such as worshipping God or honouring one's
parents, nor to those which were per se bad, such as stealing, harming others
or consorting with prostitutes, but only to those which were indifferent,
such as eating, drinking, sleeping, acquiring wealth or seeking honours.
218
The
most outspoken critic
of
Aristotle's
treatment
of
virtue was Lorenzo
Valla.
In his dialogue De vero falsoque bono
Valla,
speaking through the
interlocutor Antonio da Rho, argued
that
there
were not two vices opposed
to each virtue, as Aristotle had maintained, but
rather
for each virtue
there
was
only one contrasting
vice.
In relation to fear, Aristotle had delineated
one virtue, courage, and two
vices,
cowardice and rashness.
Valla,
however,
claimed
that
Aristotle had conflated two separate and distinct virtues under
214.
Bruni
1741, 11, pp.
140-2;
see
also
Segarizzi
1904, p. 7.
215.
Pletho
1866, col. 904: 'to (xkv aloxpov
Tráv
Seivov, av re /xeya, av re puxpov rj, TO
8'OVK
aiaxpov
dappaXeov
rrdv
a^iovvres
efvai.'
216.
Fox-Morcillo
1566, p. 223:
'Plato
vero,
quanquam
nullam
eius
mediocritatis,
quod
ego
viderim,
fecerit
mentionem,
tamen
Apuleius
in
libro
de
illius
philosophia
[sc. De Platone et eiusdogmate 11.5],
Alcinousque
[sc.
Albinus,
Didaskalikos cap. 30.4]
virtutes
in
meditullio
vitiorum
positas
ab
illo
esse
ipsumque
idem
cum
Aristotele
sensisse,
confirmant.'
217. Ibid., p. 224.
218.
Golius
1634, pp. 55-6.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008