
Moral philosophy
The
rigorous and strict morality of Stoicism appealed to certain
Renaissance scholars such as Niccolo
Niccoli,
who was portrayed by his
friend Poggio Bracciolini as a proponent of the Stoic doctrine
that
virtue
alone was sufficient to
live
the good
life.
339
Although Poggio himself at
times affected a Stoic disdain for wealth and its benefits, he usually took the
more moderate
view
that
material goods were acceptable, provided they
were used wisely and
well.
340
This ambivalent
attitude
had characterised
the humanist movement since the time of Petrarch, who had admired the
moral perfection of Stoic ethics but felt its demands were unrealistic and
inhuman.
341
Similarly, Salutati, who had given the highest praise to the
Stoics
in his De laboribus Herculis, later in his
life
began to question their
doctrines. He admitted
that
virtue and
vice
were the only moral goods and
evils
but insisted
that
the various fortunes and misfortunes which befell men
were natural, if secondary, goods and
evils,
and therefore could not be
dismissed with Stoic indifference.
342
In Alberti's dialogue Delia famiglia,
the character Lionardo refuses to admit
that
being poor is a bad thing,
claiming
that
virtue alone is sufficient to produce happiness. But these noble
sentiments are challenged by the more realistic Adovardo, who tells him
not to be such a 'Stoic' and to admit
that
poverty is a very miserable state for
everyone.
343
It was, in fact, difficult to
give
wholehearted support to Stoic
moral precepts, because the standards of behaviour demanded were so
unrelentingly high. Even the Stoics themselves had admitted
that
only an
ideal wise man could consistently
live
up to them. So, whether they
approved or disapproved of Stoic morality, most Renaissance authors
concurred in the
view,
commonly held since antiquity,
that
it was stern,
rigid, harsh and severe.
344
Even
in the Middle
Ages
Stoic moral doctrines had seemed unreasonable
to many philosophers. Thomas Aquinas, for example, had stressed
that
man
was
composed of a body as
well
as a soul and therefore needed certain
material goods merely to keep alive.
345
The Epicurean humanist Cosma
339.
Poggio
Bracciolini
1964—9,1,
p. 83 (De nobilitate): 'Non
eget
alterius
ope aut
fortunae
adminiculis
virtus
. . . cum in ea
satis
sit
praesidii
ad
bene
beateque
vivendum.'
340.
Poggio
Bracciolini
1984-,
11, p. 43: 'si
opes,
divitie,
dignitates
. . .
ofFerantur
honeste,
non
arbitror
ullo
modo
esse
reiciendas'.
341.
Petrarch
1955, pp.
22-215
(Secretum); see
also
Foster
1984, pp.
163-73.
342.
Salutati
1951,1, p. 311:
'[Stoici]
super
alios
ad
vere
virtutis
essentiam
. . .
accedebant';
1891—1911,
in, p. 417:
'Nichil
malum,
nisi
turpe
moraliter
fateor.
Naturaliter
autem
et
secundum
fortunam
multa
mala
sunt';
see
also
Witt
1983, pp.
358—67.
343.
Alberti
1969a,
pp.
96—7.
344.
Salutati
1891-1911,11, p. 292;
Barnaba
Senese
1979, p. 39:
Bruni
1928, p. 26 (Isagogicon);
Poggio
Bracciolini
1984- n
5
P- 17;
Giorgi
1525, sig. D v
r
;
Vettori
1584, p. 582;
Montaigne
1965, p. 218
(i-33).
345.
Summa
theologica 1—11.59.3 and 11—11.125.4;
see
a
ls°
Baron
1938b,
p. 3.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008