
374
Moral
philosophy
honour to be trod in the dust, he shall find
God
justly
angry with him for his
want
of anger.'
424
Pierre
Charron,
whose commitment to Neostoicism was combined with
and tempered by his interest in philosophical scepticism, had learnt from the
bloody
conflicts between Catholics and Protestants that dogmatic religious
commitment was no guarantee of virtuous conduct. He therefore
concluded that piety was completely distinct from probity, although both
were necessary for the good life.
425
Since in his view moral virtue had
nothing to do with merit or grace, he was able to present the tenets of
pagan
philosophers such as Seneca and Epictetus alongside the teachings of
Christianity
without adapting one to the other. By treating morality and
religion as two separate and autonomous spheres,
Charron
distinguished
himself from other Neostoic philosophers and took a stance which would
increasingly characterise the study of ethics.
EPICUREAN
ETHICS:
THE
SUPREME
GOOD
For
most medieval and Renaissance moral philosophers, Epicureanism was
the unacceptable face of classical ethics. Of the four major ancient
philosophical schools, Epicureanism had the worst reputation and the least
influence.
426
The Epicurean doctrine which aroused the most hostility was
the belief that pleasure was the supreme good. Because Epicurus regarded
the attainment of pleasure
(rjSovrj)
as the ultimate goal of life, he was
frequently
vilified as a sensual hedonist. But although he did not deny the
importance of
gratifying
the
senses,
he in fact identified the highest pleasure
with the complete absence of bodily pain and mental affliction.
427
He
furthermore regarded the pains and pleasures of the mind as greater than
those
of the body.
428
For Epicurus the highest pleasure, and thus the
supreme good, was an absolute tranquillity and peace of mind (arapa£ia),
which when attained by the wise man would continue to make him happy
even while his body was being tortured.
429
Epicurus
also held that although
in general pleasure was to be sought and pain avoided,
those
pleasures which
brought
with them greater pains were to be avoided, while
those
pains
which resulted in greater pleasures were to be sought.
430
Since it was
424.
Ibid.,
vi, p. 437 (ch. 15). For Aristotle's position on anger, see
Nicomachean
Ethics
111.8
(in6
b
23-
ni7
a
9) and p. 365 above.
425.
Charron
1824,11,
p. 148
(11.5):
'ce sont deux
choses
bien distinctes, et qui ont leurs resorts divers, que
la
piété et probité, la religion et la preud'hommie, la devotion et la conscience'; see also
Kogel
1972,
pp.
50-76.
426. Radetti 1889; D. C. Allen 1944; Kristeller 1965a, p. 36;
Garin
1959; Pagnoni 1974.
427.
Vatican Saying 33;
Cicero,
De
Jinibus
1.37-8. 428. Diogenes Laertius,
x.137.
429.
Ibid.,
x.
118;
Cicero,
Tusculan
Disputations
11.7-17.
430. Diogenes Laertius, x. 129.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008